АвтоАвтоматизацияАрхитектураАстрономияАудитБиологияБухгалтерияВоенное делоГенетикаГеографияГеологияГосударствоДомДругоеЖурналистика и СМИИзобретательствоИностранные языкиИнформатикаИскусствоИсторияКомпьютерыКулинарияКультураЛексикологияЛитератураЛогикаМаркетингМатематикаМашиностроениеМедицинаМенеджментМеталлы и СваркаМеханикаМузыкаНаселениеОбразованиеОхрана безопасности жизниОхрана ТрудаПедагогикаПолитикаПравоПриборостроениеПрограммированиеПроизводствоПромышленностьПсихологияРадиоРегилияСвязьСоциологияСпортСтандартизацияСтроительствоТехнологииТорговляТуризмФизикаФизиологияФилософияФинансыХимияХозяйствоЦеннообразованиеЧерчениеЭкологияЭконометрикаЭкономикаЭлектроникаЮриспунденкция

Definition of Comparative Law

Читайте также:
  1. Classical definition of probability
  2. Comparative and Historical method
  3. Comparative and Superlative Adjectives
  4. Comparative Law
  5. COMPARATIVE LAW: METHOD, SCIENCE, DISCIPLINE
  6. Conversion, its definition.
  7. Definition 6. A square matrix is said to be non-degenerate, if it has nonzero determinant.
  8. Definition of a word
  9. Definition of functions of several variables
  10. Definition of meaning. Meaning and concept. Different approaches to study of meaning.
  11. Definition of Phoneme

What is comparative law? The answer to this seemingly simple

question has been attempted by more than one generation of

comparative lawyers. In truth, the answer can not be absolutely straightforward.

Comparative law is not, obviously, a school of the modern

general theory of law in the sense in which we speak of, for example,

the neo-Kantian or existential philosophy of law. The socio-political,

practical-applied, scientific-theoretical, and instructional-pedagogical

roles of comparative law in the legal life of various countries shows

that it grew as an integral movement and formed as an autonomous

scientific orientation on legal research.

The term “comparative law” has a triple meaning: a method, a

science, and an instructional discipline.

Comparative law as a method is one of the important scientific

means of studying legal phenomena. Thanks to the application of the

comparative method, it becomes possible to elicit the general, the special,

and the unique in the legal systems of the modern day.

Comparative law as a science is the aggregate of scientific

knowledge about modern legal systems represented materially by the

multiplicity of books, pamphlets, articles, and scholarly papers.

Comparative law as an instructional discipline is the subject

of teaching in higher educational institutions.

In this work comparative law is regarded primarily as a science

and as an instructional discipline. Questions of the use of the comparative

method to resolve specific scientific-practical legal problems, that is,

“comparative legislation”, and the tasks and objects of the use of the

comparative method, that is, the theory of the comparative method, a re

not considered in this study. When using the term “comparative law”,

we speak here of the science of comparative law, the integrated and

comparative study of modern legal systems, and also about (lie

Instructional discipline.

Comparative law as a science and as a course of study in each

country has its specific features. Various doctrinal approaches of

scholars exist in various countries to the subject of comparative law,

and there often are several schools and orientations even within (lie

same country.

The very name “comparative law” has semantic nuances. The

term “comparative” is used in the traditional meaning but it is not the

same in the various languages: the French speak of “droid compare".;

the English and the Americans, of “comparative law”; the Germans, of

“Rechtsvergleichung”, and so on. There are considerable divergences

to be observed not only among the various languages, but even within a

single language: comparative law, law comparison, comparative

jurisprudence; Rechtsvergleichung, vergleichende Rechtslehre,

vergleichcnde Rechtswissenschaft. The term most widely used in most

countries of the world is “comparative law”.

The detractors of comparative law often have used the argil 11 lei 11

that such a law, as a system of norms, does not exist. But no one has

ever asserted that comparative law is a branch of positive law. “Any

doubts relative to comparative law disappear”, stressed (lie English

comparatist, H. Gutteridgc, “if one recognizes that this expression means

national legal systems which incorporated the historical specific features

of the development of each of the Western countries.

The position of the German comparativist, L.-J. Constantinescu, is

typical. Citing the views of the aforesaid two orientations, he wrote:

“One can find arguments in support of both views. Everything depends

on how they define law and its place in science. If it is reduced to a

mental operation comparing similar objects, it seems that the roots of

comparative law do indeed go back to the remote past. And, on the contrary,

if one understands it to be activity for the purpose of the consistent

approximation of legal systems, one must concur with Pollock”.

Thus it historically happened that unlike, for example, the general

theory of law or the philosophy of law, comparative law was formed as

an autonomous scientific discipline only during the second half of the

nineteenth century or, more precisely, in the last quarter of that century.

The origin and formalization of comparative law as an autonomous

branch of legal science is inseparable from the vast complex of sociopolitical

changes which accompanied the development of national legal

systems. This relatively late rise of comparative law is to be explained

by two factors, the rather obvious link between which individual

comparativists either do not recognize or in any event do not emphasize

specially. One factor is of a social nature, and the other is linked with

the inner logic of the development of legal science. This second factor

is often advanced to the forefront in comparativist writings. An example

is the position of Constantinescu, the author of one of the most detailed

surveys of the history of the origin and development of comparative

law. An analogous view is held by other major figures of legal

comparativistics, such as Gutteridge, David, Rheinstein, and others.

The need for comparative law to a certain extent derived from

the inner logic of the development of the legal sciences. In the early

nineteenth century national unilateralism and limitedness became

increasingly impossible. Legal development had reached a high level

and national legal systems had been formed; interest could not fail to

increase in the study of foreign legislation, and in this connection two

trends were visible: on one hand, the commonality and similarity of

national legislation was stressed, and on the other, greater attention

was devoted to the differences between it.

The works which appeared early in the nineteenth century

endeavored to conceptualize legal phenomena on the historical comparative

plane and prepared a favorable foundation on which the

science of comparative law later took root.

Comparative law also received new impulses from other sciences

which at the time had recourse to comparative analysis. This affected

even the natural sciences: comparative anatomy, comparative physiology,

and later, comparative linguistics.' All the research of these science's

developed simultaneously with comparative law and facilitated its coming

into being.

At the same time, the reasons for the solitary and intensive

development of comparative law into an autonomous discipline should

be sought above all in its practical aims and not in methodological

argumentation. The first steps along the path of comparative law (jus

as the beginning of any scientific knowledge) were made, as Sir

Frederick Pollock, the English jurist, said, for a purely practical purpose,

Historical reality itself exerted a decisive influence on the origins

of comparative law, that is, the internationalization of the economy, I lie

development of international relations, trade links, an increase of the

export of capital and the expansion of colonialism, which led to legal

science being forced to transcend the framework of national law and

national legislation.

These social factors placed comparative law on a practical

foundation. The purely theoretical approach was combined with a

practical-applied one. Therefore the Russian scholar, F. V. Taranovskii,

had every reason to write that “comparative law is the most important

legacy which the nineteenth century left to legal science. Reasons of a

dual nature led to the renaissance and facilitated the development in

the nineteenth century of this new orientation of legal thought

theoretical and practical”.

One should note in this connection the institutionalization of

comparative legal research, the growing separation of comparative law

from the history of law and from the theory and philosophy of law.

Scholarly institutions emerged, such as the Society of Comparative

Legislation in France, founded in 1869 for practical purposes; the Society

of Comparative Legislation in England, created in 1898, the International

Association of Comparative Law and Science of the National Economy,

established at Berlin in 1899, and others.

Institutionalization was expressed further in the creation and

publication of specialized journals, the regular convocation of international

congresses, and the like. Considerations of a practical nature led in

certain countries (France, Germany, England, the United States) to

incorporating comparative law into the programme of legal education,

the basis of which comprised research into foreign legal systems and

the formation of special chairs of comparativistic nature.


1 | 2 | 3 | 4 |

Поиск по сайту:



Все материалы представленные на сайте исключительно с целью ознакомления читателями и не преследуют коммерческих целей или нарушение авторских прав. Студалл.Орг (0.016 сек.)